perspectives - ACI Fonction

4 downloads 55 Views 329KB Size Report
(opposed to Auguste Comte's 'Scale of the. Sciences') (see figure), where developmental psychology provided the foundations for logic and mathematics, and ...
PERSPECTIVES OPINION

Neural foundations of logical and mathematical cognition Olivier Houdé and Nathalie Tzourio-Mazoyer Brain-imaging techniques have made it possible to explore the neural foundations of logical and mathematical cognition. These techniques are revealing more than simply where these high-order processes take place in the human cortex. Imaging is beginning to answer some of the oldest questions about what logic and mathematics are, and how they emerge and evolve through visuospatial cognition, language, executive functions and emotion.

Since Aristotle, it has been argued that the essence of the human mind is the ‘logos’, which encompasses both logic and language. Early in the twentieth century, the psychologist Jean Piaget (BOX 1) pointed out that logic is the highest form of biological adaptation1 (see also related speculations about the neurobiology of mathematics2), but it was not until recently, with the advent of brain-imaging techniques, that it became possible to start exploring the neural foundations of logical reasoning and mathematical computation. Here we examine logical and mathematical cognition together: first, because they are often considered as the two main components of the most abstract form of intelligence3 and second, to compare how they emerge and evolve in children and adults, through basic processes such as visuospatial cognition, language, executive functions and emotion. Rather than a modular view of cognition4,5, which attempts to isolate these processes in the human mind, we focus on interactions between them, as evidenced by brain-imaging techniques. Our aim is not to be exhaustive,

NATURE REVIEWS | NEUROSCIENCE

but to address core issues and different views, in the hope of providing new research perspectives on the problem. Logical cognition

According to Piaget1 (BOX 1), logical cognition, qualified as ‘hypotheticodeductive’, sets in during adolescence, at about the age of 14 or 15. The most canonical form of logical cognition is the so-called ‘if–then’ conditional reasoning. In this section, we address three issues6: Do we reason with logic, as argued by Piaget? Why do we make reasoning errors? Can emotions help us reason? Do we reason with logic? According to Braine and O’Brien7, humans possess a mental or natural logic, which is defined as a set of simple inference rules that are required to understand language and to reason about everyday practical matters: for example,‘if p then q; p = > q’. The rules of mental logic are universal; they are present in all languages, are fully mastered by adults, and are understood early by children. On the other hand, Johnson-Laird8 has proposed the opposing view that we can reason without logico-linguistic rules. He illustrates his position with syllogisms and conditionals, the terms of which play parts on the stage of a mental model, like actors in a theatre. For example, artists, beekeepers and chemists are the actors in the following syllogism: ‘All artists are beekeepers. All beekeepers are chemists. Which conclusion, if any, follows from these two premises?’ This reasoning process, so the argument goes, takes place in a visuospatial workspace rather than in a

logico-linguistic one. Neither view — mental logic or mental model — has supplanted the other one in cognitive psychology, as both are supported by behavioural data7,8. What we lacked in the past for directly testing these two opposing theories were brain-imaging techniques. With these new tools, one of the crucial questions is: does correct performance on deductive tasks recruit linguistic or visuospatial brain areas? Reasoning with a mental model, as JohnsonLaird has claimed, should recruit a neural network devoted to mental imagery9. Going beyond the opposition of both models in cognitive psychology, Goel et al.10–12 have obtained compelling imaging data in support of a ‘dual-mechanism theory’. According to this theory, different brain networks — logico-linguistic or visuospatial — are activated depending on whether the reasoning problem to be solved has semantic content. On the one hand, they have shown that the left inferior frontal gyrus (Broca’s area) is systematically activated by deductive logic, and that other activations that participate in this type of reasoning lie mostly in the left hemisphere, especially in temporal (including Wernicke’s area) and frontal regions. These results confirm the strong connection between deductive logic and linguistic brain areas, as predicted by Braine and O’Brien’s theory of mental logic7, that is already present in Aristotle’s definition of logos (logic and language). They are also in line with neuropsychological data showing that patients with damage to the left hemisphere in regions associated with linguistic ability are impaired at comprehending visuospatial logical relations13. Moreover, the results of Goel et al. are consistent with the fact that, following action and visuospatial cognition in both phylogeny and ontogeny14,15, deductive logic takes a leap forward when verbal formulation becomes possible. On the other hand, Goel et al. have also shown that when deductive judgement is applied to syllogisms without semantic content (for example, ‘All P are B. All B are C.

VOLUME 4 | JUNE 2003 | 1

PERSPECTIVES So, all P are C’), a bilateral parieto-frontal network is involved in addition to the previous temporal and frontal activations. This activation pattern is more consistent with a visuospatial representation of the problem in working memory9, as predicted by JohnsonLaird’s theory of mental models8. This example clearly shows that the use of brain-imaging techniques could enable us to go beyond the theoretical opposition between models, which has remained unsolved by purely behavioural studies.

Before training

Error "If there is not a red square on the left, then there is a yellow circle on the right"

After training Logical response

Why do we make reasoning errors? Contrary to Piaget’s theory1, which postulated a logical stage of thinking by the age of 14 or 15 (BOX 1), new studies on the cognitive psychology of reasoning have shown that adolescents and adults consistently make deduction errors in certain situations, owing to what are called ‘reasoning biases’16. So, a crucial task for cognitive and developmental neuroscience is to study not only errors and biases in human reasoning, but also the so-called ‘de-biasing mechanisms’16 that redirect our mind to logical thought. In the seventeenth century, the French philosopher René Descartes had already noted this problem when he proposed his method — a set of ‘rules for the direction of the mind’17. The ideal psychological model for this type of study is experimental training. We devised a de-biasing model using a deductive reasoning task with negative conditionals (for example, ‘if not p, then q’), where all participants first relied on a perceptual strategy and therefore responded erroneously, obtaining an error rate as high as 90% (REF. 18) (FIG. 1).

Figure 1 | Imaging error-inhibition training in a deductive logic task. The results from positron emission tomography show a clear reconfiguration of the activation pattern, which shifted from the posterior part of the brain when subjects relied on an erroneous perceptual strategy (right, top) to the prefrontal part when they accessed deductive logic (right, bottom). Adapted, with permission, from REF. 18  (2000) The MIT Press.

The task was to read a rule such as ‘If there is not a red square on the left, then there is a yellow circle on the right’, and to select two geometrical shapes that would make the rule false. Most people spontaneously put a red square on the left of a yellow circle, thinking they were answering correctly. This logic error is caused by what Evans has called the perceptualmatching bias19. Subjects answer using the shapes that are mentioned in the rule instead of reasoning according to the logical truth

table, which would lead them to choose a case where the antecedent of the rule is true (not a red square) and the consequent is false (not a yellow circle); for example, a blue square to the left of a green diamond. The logical response therefore requires resisting the elements perceived in the rule; that is, inhibiting the perceptual-matching bias. This is a good example of abstraction — a controlled and analytical kind of processing that occurs when our brain can break away from perception

Box 1 | Jean Piaget (1896–1980) The child psychologist Jean Piaget was the first to point out that logical cognition is the highest form of biological adaptation in the human brain. In the mid-twentieth century, Piaget described a ‘Circle of the Sciences’ (opposed to Auguste Comte’s ‘Scale of the Sciences’) (see figure), where developmental psychology provided the foundations for logic and mathematics, and was itself grounded on biology, biochemistry, chemistry and physics. But it was not until after Piaget’s death, with the advent of brainimaging techniques, that it became possible to study the biological foundations of logical and mathematical cognition. Using a purely behavioural method, Piaget related the diverse fields of human knowledge, especially logic and mathematics, to the developing minds of children1. In his theory, infants begin by

2

| JUNE 2003 | VOLUME 4

building a logic of direct action on the world — what Piaget called sensorimotor intelligence. They then build complex action systems that help them create concrete representations of objects at about age two (pre-operational intelligence). By the time they are six to eight years old, children construct a logic of concrete operations on objects, events and people (in particular, the number conservation stage). Building on this concrete logic, children after the age of 12 invent a formal, hypotheticodeductive logic that Piaget called formal operations, which has much in common with the rational logic of scientists and mathematicians. Although Piaget is one of the best-known and most influential cognitive scientists in the educational world, the validity of his stage theory is now under debate in developmental psychology23.

www.nature.com/reviews/neuro

PERSPECTIVES (which relies more heavily on automatic and heuristic processes). Surprisingly, although logical abstraction is an indisputably crucial feature of human thinking, it has only recently been studied using brain imaging18. Since the pioneering work of Raichle and his colleagues20, imaging research on cognitive training has mainly been devoted to the study of practice-related changes during the setting in of automatic processes (such as verb generation20 and visuomotor sequence learning21) and not to the contrasting study of control resulting from logical abstraction. To study the perceptual matching bias, we hypothesized that adults, like children during the acquisition of elementary cognitive abilities22,23, have two competing strategies in their mental workspace24 — one logical and one perceptual — but they have trouble inhibiting the perceptual one. This is not really a question of mental logic per se1,7, but one of executive control25,26, in this case, cognitive inhibition. To show this, we used three training conditions: inhibition of the perceptual strategy (including emotional warnings about the error risk), logical explanation and simple task repetition (which corresponds to practice). Only inhibition training proved effective in reducing errors: the success rate increased from 10% to above 90%. This means that an executive inhibitory mechanism is what these adults were lacking, not logic or practice. We then carried out an imaging study using positron emission tomography (PET) to see what was happening before and after training in the perceptual-matching biasinhibition condition18. We found a clear shift in activity from the posterior part of the brain before training to the prefrontal part after training (FIG. 1). So, several concurrent reasoning strategies might compete at any time, even during adulthood, in such a way that perceptual responses often override logical ones, and cognitive inhibition turns out to be the key that opens the door to deductive logic. As a whole, these results argue for individual variability in human reasoning, selection by training and dynamic-network cognition27. In the same vein, Goel and Dolan28 recently conducted a functional magnetic resonance imaging (fMRI) study on bias inhibition and semantic beliefs.Although deductive reasoning is a closed system, our beliefs about the world can influence validity judgements in syllogistic tasks16 (for example, the invalid but believable conclusion ‘Some machines are not computers’ follows from the premises ‘All calculators are machines’ and ‘All computers are calculators’). In this study, the authors showed that the right lateral prefrontal cortex was specifically

NATURE REVIEWS | NEUROSCIENCE

Box 2 | Functional brain development: a new perspective Recently, Johnson32 presented an overview of functional brain development in humans. He distinguished three perspectives that might shed light on the processes of psychological change and clarify the functional consequences of neuroanatomical changes during cognitive and perceptual development: the maturational perspective, the interactive specialization approach and the skill-learning hypothesis. We propose a fourth perspective that we think is crucial for understanding functional brain development, particularly during the acquisition of logical and mathematical abilities by pre-school and school children. Johnson states that the third perspective is a skill-learning model in which the cortical activation pattern changes with the acquisition of new skills throughout the lifespan. In the example used in Johnson’s illustration, where human adults are performing a visuomotor sequence-learning task21, there is decreasing activation of the prefrontal cortex, accompanied by increasing activation of more posterior regions (parietal areas). But positron emission tomography evidence of the opposite neural reconfiguration — a change of brain activation from posterior to prefrontal areas — was obtained with our executive type of learning as human adults performed a logical reasoning task18 (FIG. 1). This posterior-to-anterior shift is what we propose to add to Johnson’s list as a fourth perspective. We suggest that this type of change might occur during the acquisition of new cognitive skills by pre-school and school children, particularly when they must learn to inhibit a perceptual error or to activate a logical strategy1,23.

activated in the condition where people had to inhibit belief-based responses, in contrast to neutral or facilitatory conditions. Cognitive inhibition is therefore a key executive function in adult reasoning. Developmental psychology studies also indicate that children often fail to inhibit reasoning biases, especially perceptual ones (or semantic belief biases), and that they are even more receptive to bias-inhibition training than are adults1,23,29. Given the considerable growth of the prefrontal cortex in the course of brain evolution30,31, an important research endeavour in developmental neuroscience is to look into this type of posterior-to-anterior functional reconfiguration18 to find out whether this is one of the processes through which logical cognition emerges and evolves. This perspective is lacking in some previous accounts32 of functional brain development in humans (BOX 2), yet this posterior-to-anterior reconfiguration brought about by inhibitory control might be the neural correlate of human abstraction, the ability to break away from perceptual biases during cognitive development. Recently, Casey and her collaborators explored the neural basis of the development of inhibitory control in children, combining fMRI with a parametric manipulation of a visuomotor go–no-go task33. They showed that successful response inhibition was associated with stronger activation of prefrontal and parietal regions in children than in adults. This new research trend in developmental neuroscience34 should be pursued using logic tasks that tend to trigger perceptual or semantic errors23. Another challenge for the cognitive neuroscience of logical reasoning is to clarify the topographical layout of deductive logic,

language and executive control (especially inhibition) in the left inferior frontal gyrus. As stated above, the left inferior frontal gyrus is involved in deductive logic. But this cortical area is also known to be devoted to language, particularly in semantic-knowledge selection35,36, and to cognitive inhibition in working memory, as suggested by Konishi37–39, Jonides40, D’Esposito41 and their collaborators. For all of these functions, authors often report what they call a left ventrolateral prefrontal activation that, in fact — and more exactly — lies in Broca’s area (FIG. 2). The implication of the left inferior frontal region during this set of cognitive activities can be understood in different ways. One interpretation would be that several kinds of neural activity support these different cognitive activities. Indeed, one of the limits of brain imaging is that an observed activation signal, although strongly correlated with local field potentials, might correspond to excitatory, inhibitory or both types of synaptic activity 42,43. A second interpretation would be that, in line with Luria44, left inferior frontal involvement illustrates the tight links in the human frontal lobes between language, inhibitory control and action. In our PET experiment18, Broca’s area was indeed activated when subjects became able to inhibit their perceptual error after training and to change their mode of action during reasoning. A third interpretation would be that left frontal activation reflects an underlying neural computation that is required not only for deductive logic, but also for language and cognitive inhibition in working memory. This computation would be modulated by the components of the involved networks, as postulated in ‘neural context’ theory45.

VOLUME 4 | JUNE 2003 | 3

PERSPECTIVES

Figure 2 | Prefrontal activation during deductive-logic and cognitive-inhibition tasks. The activation foci are superimposed on sagittal (top) and horizontal (bottom) sections. Within the left inferior frontal gyrus, the opercular part is shown in purple and the triangular part is shown in pink. This selection of brain-imaging studies (each coloured dot corresponds to a different study) investigated syllogistic reasoning (blue)10–12, bias inhibition in conditional reasoning (purple)18, and inhibition in the Wisconsin Card Sorting Test (yellow and red)37,38 and in a verbal working-memory task (green)40.

Whatever the actual explanation, the fact that Broca’s area is implicated in different cognitive activities should lead us to reconsider the boundaries of what have often been seen as airtight domains. This fact challenges a restricted modular view of brain functioning 4,5. Can emotions help us reason? Except for Damasio’s contribution from clinical neuropsychology 46,47, this question has not attracted much attention in cognitive neuroscience despite its potentially great implications for educational policies. Against Descartes’ well-known opposition between reason and emotion17, Damasio offers eloquent support for the view that

4

| JUNE 2003 | VOLUME 4

‘good use of reason’ depends on emotion and self-feeling. Studying patients with brain injuries, he has shown that emotion probably assists reasoning, especially when it comes to personal and social matters that involve risk and conflict. In this framework, the oldest and most famous case is Phineas Gage48 (FIG. 3a). The study of Gage’s lesion and other more recent cases shows that ventromedial prefrontal damage causes a defect in reasoning/decision making, emotion and self-feeling46,47. In line with Damasio’s contribution, we recently hypothesized49 that there might be a close tie between emotion, self-feeling and reasoning error inhibition in the intact human brain. In our previous PET study18, training in our matching bias-inhibition condition included emotional warnings about the error risk, which were not present in the logic-only training condition. We compared the impact of these two training conditions and found that, in the matching bias-inhibition one, activation was observed not only in the left lateral prefrontal cortex, but also in the right ventromedial prefrontal cortex (FIG. 3b). That is, the activation was present exactly in the location of the lesion in Gage (FIG. 3a) and in Damasio’s patients46–48,50. These data show that, in healthy subjects, this area participates in getting the mind on the ‘logical track’51, where it can put the instruments of deduction to good use. Note that the right ventromedial prefrontal cortex was not activated in the logic-only trained subjects who received no emotional warnings and were unable to inhibit their reasoning error. This cortical area could therefore be the emotional component of the brain’s error-correction device. To be more precise, it could correspond, together with the anterior cingulate cortex52, to the brain area that detects the conditions under which logical reasoning errors might occur. Other recent imaging studies have stressed the role of the medial part of the prefrontal cortex in the emotional evaluation of error risks in domains related to logical cognition, notably, in the rapid processing of monetary gains and losses during economic reasoning53. To further our understanding of this issue, cognitive-affective and developmental neuroscience should study exactly how the right ventromedial prefrontal cortex is involved in the emergence of logical cognition. Mathematical cognition

Do we perform arithmetic operations with language brain areas or with visuospatial brain areas? How might these areas interact in arithmetic computation? Some information on these issues has been obtained through behavioural studies on the mathematical

competence of children after two years of age and preverbal infants, and even of monkeys. Bridging the gap between these behavioural studies and imaging data on the arithmetic capabilities of adults is highly fruitful for cognitive neuroscience. When do mathematics emerge? According to Piaget’s theoryof developmental stages1 (BOX 1), mathematical cognition sets in during childhood, at about the age of 7 or 8. Since then, many authors have reported evidence of precocious mathematical capacities, especially in arithmetic computation23,54. So, Wynn55,56 showed that preverbal human infants can do simple operations such as 1 + 1 = 2 or 2 – 1 = 1, an ability that has also been shown in monkeys by Hauser and his colleagues57,58. Wynn’s experiments, which used a violation-ofexpectation model, have established that 5-month-old infants can detect the error in violations such as 1 + 1 = 1 and 1 + 1 = 3. Their longer times looking at these ‘magical events’ are taken as a testimony to the ability of these children to calculate 1 + 1 = 2. According to Wynn, the existence of these numerical abilities so early in infancy indicates that humans might possess an innate capacity to perform simple arithmetic computations, which lays the foundations for the later development of higher mathematical abilities. But authors like Simon59 have refuted this conclusion, arguing for a non-numerical, purely visuospatial account that interprets Wynn’s data in terms of object-based attention. Simon contends that with the new tools of brain imaging to add to our experimental methods, we have reached the point where we should be able to discover how mathematical cognition arises from “a brain without numbers”60. Wynn’s findings are robust and consistent56 and show that infants think about numerical events before they speak. At the very least, preverbal infants can be considered to use a ‘visuospatial arithmetic’. To address this issue, we conducted cross-linguistic experiments using the same violation-of-expectation model with 2–3-year-old children, just after articulated language emerges in child development61. Measuring children’s verbal reactions, we showed that, although there is a general arithmetic ability for small numbers that is shared by preverbal infants55,56 and monkeys57,58, the ontogeny of this initial knowledge in humans follows different performance patterns, depending on what language the children speak (BOX 3). This is a cross-linguistic demonstration of the early shift from visuospatial arithmetic (in monkeys and human infants) to symbolic–linguistic arithmetic (in young children). Spelke and Tsivkin62,

www.nature.com/reviews/neuro

PERSPECTIVES

How do adult brains compute arithmetic? According to Dehaene and his colleagues63, exact arithmetic (for example, multiplication tables) is based on a linguistic representation and relies on perisylvian language areas. By contrast, magnitude representations of numbers rely on the parietal cortex, the visuospatial site of a specific biological foundation for ‘number sense’ in adults, preverbal infants and monkeys. We conducted a PET study aimed at disclosing the functional anatomy of the two basic operations that are involved in mental calculation — arithmetic fact retrieval and actual computation — and the respective roles of the visuospatial and language brain areas64. Subjects had to perform three tasks: read digits, retrieve simple arithmetic facts from memory (for example, what is 2 x 4?), and compute complex operations (for example, what is 32 x 24?). Compared with the reading task, the retrieval task engaged a left parieto-premotor circuit, perhaps the developmental trace of a fingercounting strategy that, by extension, mediates numerical knowledge in adults. Indeed, Siegler 65 has stressed that children use various overlapping strategies to solve arithmetic problems: counting with or without fingers, retrieval, decomposition, and so on. In addition to this basic network, the retrieval task involved a naming network that included the left anterior insula and the right cerebellar cortex. But contrary to the predictions of Dehaene and his colleagues63, it did not involve the perisylvian language areas, which were significantly deactivated compared with a rest condition. The arithmetic computation task not only relied on this retrieval network, but also involved a bilateral parietofrontal network (which is probably in charge of holding multi-digit numbers in visuospatial working memory) and the bilateral inferior temporal gyrus (which is probably important for visual mental imagery)9. Overall, these results provide strong evidence for the involvement of visuospatial representations in exact computations that require complex

NATURE REVIEWS | NEUROSCIENCE

a

b

24 20 16 12 8 4 0 –4 –8 –12 –16

∆NrCBF

who conducted a training experiment with Russian–English bilingual college students, also showed that a specific language (the training language) can affect representations of large numbers. In light of these developmental findings, a key question for imaging in adults is determining whether arithmetic — not only simple additive problems, but also multiplication with multi-digit numbers, for example — recruits language areas, or whether it is still supported mainly by visuospatial systems as in monkeys and infants.

Figure 3 | The right ventromedial prefrontal cortex and its relation to emotion and reason. a | Reconstruction of the location of Phineas Gage’s lesion in the right ventromedial prefrontal cortex. b | Variations in normalized regional cerebral blood flow (∆NrCBF) measured by positron emission tomography in the right ventromedial prefrontal cortex of control subjects, depending on whether they could (purple bars) or could not (pink bars) inhibit a reasoning error on a logic task. Each bar corresponds to one subject. Adapted, with permission, from REF. 49  (2001) Elsevier Science.

operations. They are consistent with numerous lesion studies in human, showing the crucial role of the parietal lobe in mental calculation and number processing66. Recent research on the cerebral bases of number in monkeys has confirmed the existence of a ‘single-neuron arithmetic’ in parietofrontal areas67. Nieder et al.68 reported the discovery of number-encoding neurons in the lateral prefrontal cortex of the macaque brain. They showed monkeys a sequence of two visual displays, each consisting of up to five dots. The monkeys were trained to decide whether the two displays contained the same number of items. Their ability to generalize when presented with various new displays was also tested. The results showed that the macaques attended only to number; it did not matter whether the displays were equivalent in terms of area, shape, linear arrangement or density. Together with an earlier report of numberresponsive neurons in the monkey parietal cortex69, this work opens up the possibility of studying the cerebral bases of elementary arithmetic at the single-cell level. At the highest level of behavioural complexity, we used PET to study the brain of a calculating prodigy, Rüdiger Gamm70,71.

Gamm is remarkable in that he has the ability to calculate, for example, the quotient of two primes to 60 decimal places with incredible accuracy. We found that, unlike control subjects, Gamm’s calculation processes recruited a system of brain areas that are implicated in episodic memory, which included the right medial frontal and parahippocampal gyri (FIG. 4). This finding indicates that experts might develop a way of exploiting the unlimited storage capacity of long-term memory to retain task-relevant information, such as the sequence of steps and intermediate results that are needed for complex arithmetic operations. By contrast, the rest of us rely on the limited span of working memory. Currently, we do not know whether this process is limited to mathematical cognition or if it is of a general nature. But another important finding from this study that is crucial for the present discussion was obtained by analysing the areas activated both in Gamm’s brain and control brains during calculation. Involvement of visuospatial working memory and visual imagery networks was observed in both cases, indicating that a visual short-term representation supports number retention and manipulation during arithmetic calculations.

VOLUME 4 | JUNE 2003 | 5

PERSPECTIVES

Box 3 | Ontogeny of arithmetic abilities, visuospatial cognition and language.

Error detection score

French (n = 48) 1+1=1 1+1=3

2

English (n = 32) 1+1=1 1+1=3

2-year-old children (n = 80) 1+2=4

1.5

1

1

0.5

0.5

0

1+2=4 2+1=4

2+1=4

2

1.5

3-year-old children (n = 80)

0 2 year olds

3 year olds

2 year olds 3 year olds

English

French

English

French

Some aspects of our numerical competence emerge before our linguistic competence and others emerge afterwards. At present, we do not understand how these two domains of knowledge affect each other in the course of evolution or during development58. In an attempt to resolve this issue, we measured children’s verbal reactions in a violation-of-expectation model that was previously used on preverbal infants55,56 and monkeys57. We showed that French-speaking 2-year-old children respond correctly to 1 + 1 = 1 (‘It’s not right’) but fail on 1 + 1 = 3, where they think it is fine ‘because there are lots’61. Only 3-year-old children are able to achieve verbal performance as accurate as the visual performance of 5-month-old infants and monkeys (see figure). Our interpretation of this developmental lag is that it stems from interference between early visuospatial arithmetic (in monkeys and preverbal infants) and the later acquisition of number in language; that is, the singular opposed to the plural, which encompasses all other numbers treated as a whole. In French, unlike English, the same word (un) is used to represent singularity both as a cardinal value in the ordinal sequence of number words un, deux, trois... (one, two, three...), and as an indefinite article in the singular–plural opposition un–des (a–some). The operation 1 + 1 = 3 could therefore be erroneously accepted by French 2-year-old children simply because the outcome (3) is plural and differs from the starting point (1), which is singular. We therefore suspected that the difficulty of French children on detecting the error in 1 + 1 = 3 lay in their partial conflation of the singular–plural distinction and the cardinal value system. So, our prediction was that the interference between early arithmetic abilities and number-in-language acquisition would be smaller in English-speaking than in French-speaking children. In addition, we predicted that if the singular–plural opposition was not part of the experimental design (that is, a violation in which the starting point was plural such as 2 + 1 = 4, rather than singular as in 1 + 2 = 4 or 1 + 1 = 3), the interference would disappear. These predictions were confirmed with French- and English-speaking 2- and 3-year-old children (C. Hodent , P. Bryant and O.H., unpublished data; see figure). In summary, although there is a visuospatial arithmetic ability in preverbal infants and monkeys55–58, the ontogeny of this initial knowledge follows different performance patterns, depending on what specific language72 the children speak.

These imaging data from non-expert and expert adult calculators, along with single-cell data recorded in monkeys, provide new fuel for the debate about the numerical abilities of infants55–60. As we have seen, Wynn55,56 argues for the early existence of the capacity to perform simple and exact arithmetic computations, whereas Simon59,60 and many others in the field argue for a visuospatial account of Wynn’s data. The violation-of-expectation task used by Wynn primarily requires visual imagery and visuospatial working memory, two cognitive functions that already exist in the infant’s brain. But the PET results clearly indicate that these brain functions are recruited by exact arithmetic in adults64, even in a calculating prodigy70. Consequently, visuospatial cognition and mathematical cognition are not mutually exclusive in the human brain. This means that both Wynn and Simon are right, as in monkeys, infants and adults, the

6

| JUNE 2003 | VOLUME 4

recruitment of visuospatial systems to do arithmetic is undeniable.A remaining problem in this debate is to define the breaking point between visuospatial and arithmetical processing. Hauser et al.72 recently proposed that a general kind of recursion might be the marker of high-order mathematical and linguistic abilities in humans, but the neural implementation of this process is still unknown. We have seen that language acquisition strongly interacts with arithmetic development for both small and large numbers62 (BOX 3). So, an important goal for future research is to clarify the verbal/visuospatial interaction by means of which arithmetic evolves and operates in the human brain. The first step is to explore more accurately the fine specialization of the left parietal lobe. In a recent PET study, we pointed out that when adults are making complex mental calculations, they not only recruit visuospatial areas, but also the left

Figure 4 | Imaging cortical activity in a calculating prodigy. Top view of the brain showing areas that were active both in non-expert calculators and in the calculating prodigy Rüdiger Gamm (green), and areas that were active only in Gamm’s brain (orange). The data confirm the involvement of visuospatial areas — namely the left parietofrontal network — even in a calculating prodigy. Areas activated only in Gamm’s brain included regions that are devoted to episodic memory, such as the right medial frontal and parahippocampal gyri. Adapted, with permission, from Nature Neuroscience REF. 70  (2001) Macmillan Magazines Ltd.

supramarginal gyrus — a parietal region close to the language areas that is involved in the phonological component of verbal working memory73. This region would be a good candidate for partially sustaining the interaction between verbalization and visuospatial cognition in arithmetic computation. Dehaene and his colleagues74 recently conducted an fMRI study in an attempt to clarify the topographical layout of hand-, eye-, calculation- and language-related areas in the human parietal lobe. Subjects had to perform six tasks: grasping, pointing, saccades, attention, calculation and phoneme detection. Examination of task intersections disclosed a systematic anterior-to-posterior organization of activations that were associated with grasping only, grasping and pointing, all visuomotor tasks, attention and saccades, and saccades only. Calculation yielded two distinct activations: one unique to calculation in the bilateral anterior intraparietal sulcus, mesial to the supramarginal gyrus, and the other shared with phoneme detection in the left intraparietal sulcus, mesial to the angular gyrus. According to the authors, these results imply a large cortical expansion of the inferior parietal lobe that correlates with the development of human language and calculation abilities.

www.nature.com/reviews/neuro

PERSPECTIVES Olivier Houdé and Nathalie Tzourio-Mazoyer are in the Groupe d’Imagerie Neurofonctionnelle (GIN), Unité Mixte de Recherche 6095, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, Commissariat à l’Energie Atomique, Université de Caen and Université Paris-5, France. Correspondence to O.H. e-mail: [email protected]

Conclusion and future directions

Despite these findings on logical and mathematical cognition, there are many loose ends in the field. It therefore seems appropriate to end with a list of open questions for further research. Is there a central device for logicomathematical cognition in the human brain? We have seen that deductive logic recruits mainly linguistic brain areas in a left frontotemporal network10–13, whereas arithmetic computation relies principally on visuospatial brain areas in a bilateral parietofrontal network64,70. In addition to these specific networks, a brain device shared by logic and mathematics remains to be discovered using not only arithmetic tasks but also complex mathematical reasoning tasks that require deductive-logic skills75. Is the right ventromedial prefrontal cortex involved in mathematical cognition as we know it is for logic46–51? In other words, do emotion and self-feeling help get the mind on the ‘mathematical track’, where the instruments of arithmetic (or other mathematical tools) can be put to good use? How do language, logic and mathematics interact in the human brain, especially in the left inferior frontal gyrus in the case of deductive logic10–13, involving reasoning-bias inhibition18, and in the left supramarginal gyrus in the case of arithmetical computation73, involving visuospatial cognition64,70? Resolving this issue requires finding evidence of a fine-grained anatomical specialization in these brain areas and knowing their neural context45. This question fits well with insights into the relationships between language and cognition in humans and animals, especially for numerical cognition72, which argue that in the course of evolution, the modular, domain-specific4,5 system of recursion (which developed early for specific functions such as spatial navigation) might have become domain-general, operating over a broader range of elements like numbers and words. Last, how do logical and mathematical cognition emerge and evolve from infancy to adulthood? What are the cognitive stages that involve visuospatial cognition, language, executive functions (especially inhibition) and emotion, which make up this high-order developmental process? This question specifically brings out the importance of a developmental approach in this field (BOX 1). The first steps in this imaging approach to logic and mathematics were taken through the study of training18,49 or expertise70 in adults. Although purely behavioural data from developmental psychology will certainly be brought to bear on this issue, brain-imaging studies of pre-school and school children33,34,54 should also provide invaluable information.

NATURE REVIEWS | NEUROSCIENCE

doi:10.1038/nrn1117 1.

2.

3. 4. 5. 6. 7. 8. 9.

10.

11.

12.

13. 14. 15. 16. 17.

18.

19. 20.

21.

22.

23.

24.

25. 26. 27. 28. 29.

30.

31.

Fischer, K. & Kaplan, U. in The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science Vol. 3 (ed. Nadel, L.) 679–682 (Nature Publishing Group, Macmillan, London, 2003). Changeux, J.-P. & Connes, A. Conversations on Mind, Matter, and Mathematics (Princeton Univ. Press, Princeton, 1998). Gardner, H. Frames of Mind: The Theory of Multiple Intelligences (Basic Books, New York, 1993). Fodor, J. The Modularity of Mind (The MIT Press, Cambridge, 1983). Fodor, J. The Mind Doesn’t Work That Way (The MIT Press, Cambridge, 2000). Kosslyn, S. M. & Rosenberg, R. Psychology: the Brain, the Person, the World (Allyn and Bacon, Boston, 2001). Braine, M. D. S. & O’Brien, D. P. (eds) Mental Logic (Erlbaum, Hove, 1998). Johnson-Laird, P. N. Mental models and deduction. Trends Cogn. Sci. 5, 434–442 (2001). Mellet, E., Petit, L., Denis, M. & Tzourio-Mazoyer, N. Reopening the mental imagery debate: lessons from functional anatomy. NeuroImage 8, 129–139 (1998). Goel, V., Gold, B., Kapur, S. & Houle, S. The seats of reason? An imaging study of deductive and inductive reasoning. NeuroReport 8, 1305–1310 (1997). Goel, V., Gold, B., Kapur, S. & Houle, S. Neuroanatomical correlates of human reasoning. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 10, 293–302 (1998). Goel V., Buchel, C., Frith, C. & Dolan, R. Dissociation of mechanisms underlying syllogistic reasoning. NeuroImage 12, 504–514 (2000). Wharton, C. M. & Grafman, J. Deductive reasoning and the brain. Trends Cogn. Sci. 2, 54–59 (1998). Langer, J. The descent of cognitive development. Dev. Sci. 3, 361–388 (2000). Baillargeon, R. & Wang, S. Event categorization in infancy. Trends Cogn. Sci. 6, 85–92 (2002). Evans, J. St. B. T. Bias in Human Reasoning: Causes and Consequences (Erlbaum, London, 1989). Gaukroger, S. in The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science Vol. 1 (ed. Nadel, L.) 947–950 (Nature Publishing Group, Macmillan, London, 2003). Houdé, O. et al. Shifting from the perceptual brain to the logical brain: the neural impact of cognitive inhibition training. J. Cogn. Neurosci. 12, 721–728 (2000). Evans, J. St B. T. Matching bias in conditional reasoning. Thinking Reasoning 4, 45–82 (1998). Raichle, M. E. et al. Practice-related changes in human brain functional anatomy during non-motor learning. Cereb. Cortex 4, 8–26 (1994). Sakai, K. et al. Transition of brain activation from frontal to parietal areas in visuomotor sequence learning. J. Neurosci. 18, 1827–1840 (1998). Diamond, A., Kirkham, N. & Amso, D. Conditions under which young children can hold two rules in mind and inhibit a prepotent response. Dev. Psychol. 38, 352–362 (2002). Houdé, O. Inhibition and cognitive development: object, number, categorization, and reasoning. Cogn. Dev. 15, 63–73 (2000). Dehaene S., Kerszberg M. & Changeux, J.-P. A neuronal model of a global workspace in effortful cognitive tasks. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 95, 14529–14534 (1998). Smith, E. E. & Jonides, J. Storage and executive processes in the frontal lobes. Science 283, 1657–1661 (1999). Miller, E. K. The prefrontal cortex and cognitive control. Nature Rev. Neurosci. 1, 59–65 (2000). Fuster, J. M. Linkage at the top. Neuron 21, 1223–1229 (1998). Goel, V. & Dolan, R. J. Explaining modulation of reasoning by belief. Cognition 87, 11–22 (2003). Moutier, S. Deductive reasoning and matching-bias inhibition training in school children. Curr. Psychol. Cogn. 19, 429–452 (2000). Fuster, J. The Prefrontal Cortex: Anatomy, Physiology, and Neuropsychology of the Frontal Lobe (Lippincott, New York, 1997). Bjorklund, D. F. In search of a metatheory for cognitive development (or, Piaget is dead and I don’t feel so good). Child Dev. 68, 144–148 (1997).

32. Johnson, M. H. Functional brain development in humans. Nature Rev. Neurosci. 2, 475–483 (2001). 33. Durston, S. et al. A neural basis for the development of inhibitory control. Dev. Sci. 5, 9–16 (2002). 34. Casey, B. J., Davidson, M. & Rosen, B. Functional magnetic resonance imaging: basic principles of and application to developmental science. Dev. Sci. 5, 301–309 (2002). 35. Thompson-Schill, S. L., D’Esposito, M., Aguirre, G. K. & Farah, M. J. Role of left inferior prefrontal cortex in retrieval of semantic knowledge: a reevaluation. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 94, 14792–14797 (1997). 36. Thompson-Schill, S. L., D’Esposito, M. & Kan, I. P. Effects of repetition and competition on activity in left prefrontal cortex during word generation. Neuron 23, 513–522 (1999). 37. Konishi, S. et al. Transient activation of inferior prefrontal cortex during cognitive set shifting. Nature Neurosci. 1, 80–84 (1998). 38. Konishi, S. et al. Common inhibitory mechanism in human inferior prefrontal cortex revealed by event-related functional MRI. Brain 122, 981–991 (1999). 39. Nakahara, K., Hayashi, T., Konishi, S. & Miyashita, Y. Functional MRI of macaque monkeys performing a cognitive set-shifting task. Science 295, 1532–1536 (2002). 40. Jonides, J., Smith, E. E., Marshuetz, C. & Koeppe, R. A. Inhibition in verbal working memory revealed by brain activation. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 95, 8410–8413 (1998). 41. D’Esposito, M., Postle, B. R. & Rypma, B. Prefrontal cortical contributions to working memory: evidence from event-related fMRI studies. Exp. Brain Res. 133, 2–11 (2000). 42. Logothetis, N. K., Pauls, J., Augath, M. A., Trinath, T. & Oeltermann, A. Neurophysiological investigation of the basis of the fMRI signal. Nature 412, 150–157 (2001). 43. Caesar, K., Gold, L. & Lauritzen, M. Context sensitivity of activity-dependent increases in cerebral blood flow. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 100, 4239–4244 (2003). 44. Tupper, D. E. in The Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science Vol. 2 (ed. Nadel, L.) 965–969 (Nature Publishing Group, Macmillan, London, 2003). 45. McIntosh, A. R., Rajah, M. N. & Lobaugh, N. J. Interactions of prefrontal cortex in relation to awareness in sensory learning. Science 284, 1531–1533 (1999). 46. Damasio, A. R. Descartes’ Error: Emotion, Reason, and the Human Brain (Grosset, Putnam, New York, 1994). 47. Damasio, A. R. The Feeling of What Happens: Body and Emotion in the Making of Consciousness (Harcourt Brace, New York, 1999). 48. Damasio, H, Grabowski, T., Frank, R., Galaburda, A. & Damasio, A. R. The return of Phineas Gage: clues about the brain from the skull of a famous patient. Science 264, 1102–1105 (1994). 49. Houdé, O. et al. Access to deductive logic depends on a right ventromedial prefrontal area devoted to emotion and feeling: evidence from a training paradigm. NeuroImage 14, 1486–1492 (2001). 50. Tranel, D., Bechara, A. & Denburg, N. L. Asymmetric functional roles of right and left ventromedial prefrontal cortices in social conduct, decision-making, and emotional processing. Cortex 38, 589–612 (2002). 51. Houdé, O. Consciousness and unconsciousness of logical reasoning errors in the human brain. Behav. Brain Sci. (in the press). 52. Bush, G., Luu, P. & Posner, M. I. Cognitive and emotional influences in anterior cingulate cortex. Trends Cogn. Sci. 4, 215–222 (2000). 53. Gehring, W. & Willoughby, A. The medial frontal cortex and the rapid processing of monetary gains and losses. Science 295, 2279–2282 (2002). 54. Carey, S. in Developmental Cognitive Neuroscience (eds Nelson, C. A. & Luciana, M.) 415–431 (The MIT Press, Cambridge, 2001). 55. Wynn, K. Addition and subtraction by human infants. Nature 358, 749–750 (1992). 56. Wynn, K. Findings of addition and subtraction in infants are robust and consistent. Child Dev. 71, 1535–1536 (2000). 57. Hauser, M. D., MacNeilage, P. & Ware, M. Numerical representations in primates. Proc. Natl Acad. Sci. USA 93, 1514–1517 (1996). 58. Hauser, M. D. Wild Minds: What Animals Really Think (Henry Holt, New York, 2000). 59. Simon, T. J. Reconceptualizing the origins of number knowledge: a ‘non-numerical’ account. Cogn. Dev. 12, 349–372 (1997). 60. Simon, T. J. The foundations of numerical thinking in a brain without numbers. Trends Cogn. Sci. 3, 363–365 (1998).

VOLUME 4 | JUNE 2003 | 7

PERSPECTIVES 61. Houdé, O. Numerical development: from the infant to the child. Wynn’s (1992) paradigm in 2- and 3-year-olds. Cogn. Dev. 12, 373–392 (1997). 62. Spelke, E. S. & Tsivkin, S. Language and number: a bilingual training study. Cognition 78, 45–88 (2001). 63. Dehaene, S., Spelke, E., Pinel, P., Stanescu, R. & Tsivkin, S. Sources of mathematical thinking: behavioral and brainimaging evidence. Science 284, 970–974 (1999). 64. Zago, L. et al. Neural correlates of simple and complex mental calculation. NeuroImage 13, 314–327 (2001). 65. Siegler, R. S. Emerging Minds: The Process of Change in Children’s Thinking (Oxford Univ. Press, New York, 1996). 66. Dehaene, S., Dehaene, G. & Cohen, L. Abstract representations of numbers in the animal and human brain. Trends Neurosci. 21, 355–361 (1998). 67. Dehaene, S. Single-neuron arithmetic. Science 297, 1652–1653 (2002).

8

| JUNE 2003 | VOLUME 4

68. Nieder, A., Freedman, D. J. & Miller, E. K. Representation of the quantity of visual items in the primate prefrontal cortex. Science 297, 1708–1711 (2002). 69. Sawamura, H., Shima, K. & Tanji, J. Numerical representation for action in the parietal cortex of the monkey. Nature 415, 918–922 (2002). 70. Pesenti, M. et al. Mental calculation in a prodigy is sustained by right prefrontal and medial temporal areas. Nature Neurosci. 4, 103–108 (2001). 71. Butterworth, B. What makes a prodigy? Nature Neurosci. 4, 11–12 (2001). 72. Hauser, M. D., Chomsky, N. & Fitch, W. T. The faculty of language: what is it, who has it, and how did it evolve? Science 298, 1569–1579 (2002). 73. Zago, L. & Tzourio-Mazoyer, N. Distinguishing visuospatial working memory and complex mental calculation areas within the parietal lobes. Neurosci. Lett. 331, 45–49 (2002).

74. Simon, O., Mangin, J.-F., Cohen, L., Le Bihan, D. & Dehaene, S. Topographical layout of hand, eye, calculation, and language-related areas in the human parietal lobe. Neuron 33, 475–487 (2002). 75. Lakoff, G. & Nunez, R. Where Mathematics Comes From: How the Embodied Mind Brings Mathematics into Being (Basic Books, New York, 2000).

Acknowledgements We would like to thank S. Moutier, L. Zago and B. Mazoyer for their contribution to our work on logical and mathematical cognition. Support for our work is provided by The Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique, the Commissariat à l’Energie Atomique, Université de Caen, Université Paris-5 (René-Descartes) and the Institut Universitaire de France. We are also grateful to V. Waltz for her help in preparing the manuscript.

www.nature.com/reviews/neuro

ONLINE Online links

Nature Neuroscience: http://www.nature.com/neuro Biographies

Olivier Houdé received his Ph.D. in psychology in 1991 from the University of Paris-5 (Sorbonne) and has been a professor of cognitive psychology there since 1995. He was also a guest professor at the University of Geneva from 1992 to 1995 and a junior member of the Institut Universitaire de France from 1997 to 2002. He received his M.Sc. in neuroscience in 1998 from the University of Lyon-1. Using experimental-psychology and brain-imaging techniques, his research deals with logical and mathematical cognition in children and adults (specifically, the role of cognitive inhibition in strategy selection). He is currently Head of the Cognitive Development and Functioning Group of the Neurofunctional Imaging Group (Unité Mixte de Recherche (UMR) 6095, Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique (CNRS), Commissariat à l’Energie Atomique (CEA), Caen and Paris-5 Universities). He was awarded the Dagnan-Bouveret Prize of the French Academy of Moral and Political Sciences in 2002. He is the Editor-InChief of the Dictionary of Cognitive Science. Nathalie Tzourio-Mazoyer received her M.D. (1984) and M.Sc. in neuroscience (1987) from the University of Paris-6. Board certified in nuclear medicine in 1989, she passed her habilitation thesis (research director) in 1997. As a staff scientist at the Atomic Energy Commission starting in 1992, she pioneered brain-activation studies with positron emission tomography in the Frédéric Joliot Hospital in France in the early 1990s, with special emphasis on the neural bases of language and its variability. She is currently Head of the Language and Reasoning Group of the Neurofunctional Imaging Group (UMR 6095, CNRS, CEA, Caen and Paris-5 Universities) and Coordinator of Cognitive Neuroimaging of Cyceron, a publicly funded brain-imaging and neuroscience research centre. She was awarded the Seymour Cray Prize in 1994, and the Dagnan-Bouveret Prize of the French Academy of Moral and Political Sciences in 2002.