Tomasz Miller, Warsaw University of Technology, Warsaw, Poland ...

7 downloads 0 Views 306KB Size Report
Tomasz Miller, Warsaw University of Technology, Warsaw, Poland ... (K)), for any µ, ν ∈ 乡(M), where J. +. (K) denotes the causal future of the set K. 3. .... was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation.
Causality for Nonlocal Events Tomasz Miller, Warsaw University of Technology, Warsaw, Poland & Copernicus Center for Interdisciplinary Studies, Kraków, Poland 1. Classical causal structure

2. Causal relation between probability measures

In Lorentzian geometry, the causal structure of a spacetime M is modelled by a binary relation  on M, with p  q meaning that the event p can be connected with the event q by means of a piecewise smooth future-directed causal curve (or p = q).

Drawing from the optimal transport theory adapted to the Lorentzian setting, in [1] we have proposed the following extension of the relation  onto P(M) – the space of Borel probability measures on M.

The relation  is a preorder. One calls a spacetime M causally simple if  is additionally transitive and topologically closed (as a subset of M2 ). In such case, the following ‘dual’ characterisation of  holds [1]. Theorem (Besnard, Minguzzi): Let M be a causally simple spacetime and let C(M) denote the set of all functions in Cb∞ (M) which are causal, i.e., non-decreasing along future-directed causal curves. Then for any p, q ∈ M pq

⇐⇒

∀ f ∈ C(M) f (p) ≤ f (q).

Definition: Let M be a spacetime. For µ, ν ∈ P(M) we say that µ causally precedes ν (denoted µ  ν) if there exists ω ∈ P(M2 ) such that (i) µ and ν are the left and right marginals of ω, respectively,

(ii) ω() = 1.

The existence of such an ω, called a causal coupling of measures µ and ν, encapsulates the following intuitive notion of causality for ‘spread’ probability distributions: Each infinitesimal portion of probability should travel along a worldline. Theorem [1]: Let M be a causally simple spacetime. Then  is a partial order on M and Z Z µ  ν ⇐⇒ ∀ f ∈ C(M) f dµ ≤ f dν M

⇐⇒

∀ compact K ⊆ supp µ

M

µ(K) ≤ ν(J + (K)),

for any µ, ν ∈ P(M), where J + (K) denotes the causal future of the set K.

3. Causal evolution of measures

4. Causality in noncommutative spacetimes

Let M be a globally hyperbolic spacetime and let T be a fixed Cauchy temporal function, i.e., a function T ∈ C ∞ (M) whose level sets are spacelike Cauchy hypersurfaces. A curve γ : I → M such that T (γ(t)) = t for any t ∈ I is a worldline iff

Observe that, by the Riesz representation theorem, P(M) ' S(C0 (M)), i.e., the space of states on the C ∗ -algebra C0 (M), with the pure states given by Dirac deltas δp for p ∈ M. It is then natural to ask whether the causal structure can be consistently defined for noncommutative spacetimes – understood as the spaces of pure states of noncommutative algebras. This was achieved in [4] within the framework of Lorentzian spectral triples and motivated by the following results:

∀ s, t ∈ I

s ≤ t =⇒ γ(s)  γ(t).

By analogy, we define a ‘measure-valued worldline’. Definition: A causal evolution of a measure is a map µ : I → P(M), t 7→ µt such that supp µt ⊆ T −1 (t) for all t ∈ I and, moreover, satisfying ∀s, t ∈ I

s ≤ t =⇒ µs  µt .

Example [2]: Let M = R1+n be the Minkowski spacetime and let µt := δt ⊗ ρ(t, .)λ, where λ is the Lebesgue measure on Rn and ρ : M → R is assumed to satisfy the continuity equation ∂t ρ + ∇ · (ρv) = 0 with a subluminal velocity field (kvk ≤ 1). Then t 7→ µt is a causal evolution of a measure. The following theorem provides an alternative view on the causal evolution of measures, showing that this is in fact an observer-independent notion. Theorem [3]: Consider a map t 7→ µt ∈ P(M) satisfying supp µt ⊆ T −1 (t) for all t ∈ I. Then this map is causal iff there exists a probability measure σ on the space of worldlines (endowed with a suitable topology) such that µt = (evt )# σ for all t ∈ I.

Example [4,5]: Let M be a globally hyperbolic spacetime with a spin structure S. We obtain a (commutative) Lorentzian spectral triple (A, K, D) by taking A :=RCc∞ (M), K := L2 (M, S) equipped with an indefinite inner prod¯ and D := D uct (φ, ψ) = M φψ, / = −iγ µ ∇S µ , the Dirac operator associated with S. / , a]φ) ≤ 0 for all φ ∈ K. Theorem [4]: A function a ∈ Cb∞ (M) is causal iff (φ, [D Definition [4]: For two states ω, χ ∈ S(A) we define ωχ

⇐⇒

ω(a) ≤ χ(a)

for all a ∈ A, such that ∀ φ ∈ K (φ, [D, a]φ) ≤ 0.

Let us illustrate the above concepts with a simple almost-commutative example: A = Cc∞ (M) ⊗ (C ⊕ C),

K = L2 (M, S) ⊗ C2 ,

0 m D=D / ⊗ 1 + γ ⊗ (m 0 ).

Although A is actually a commutative algebra and P (A) = M t M = M × {±}, but the off-diagonal part of D allows one to “jump” between the sheets. Theorem [5]: Let τ (γ) be the proper time along a causal curve γ in M. Two states (p, −), (q, +) ∈ P (A) are causally related with (p, −)  (q, +) iff there exists a causal curve γ giving p  q on M and such that τ (γ) ≥ π/(2 |m|). Strikingly, the numerical value π/(2 |m|), which becomes π~/(2 |m| c2 ) once the physical dimensions are restored, is precisely the half-period of Zitterbewegung – the trembling motion of a massive Dirac fermion [5].

References [1] M. Eckstein, T. Miller, Ann. Henri Poincaré, (2017). [2] M. Eckstein, T. Miller, Phys. Rev. A 95, 032106, (2017). [3] T. Miller, J. Geom. Phys. 116, 295–315, (2017). [4] N. Franco, M. Eckstein, Class. Quant. Grav. 30 135007, (2013).

Funding

[5] M. Eckstein, N. Franco, T. Miller, Phys. Rev. D 95, 061701, (2017).

The research was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation.