Why do people pay taxes? - ScienceDirect

24 downloads 1896 Views 1MB Size Report
overweight the low probability of audit. although such overweighting is not universal. The ... reasons behind individual tax compliance behavior remains limited.
Journal

of Public Economics

48 (1992)

21-38.

North-Holland

Why do people pay taxes? James Aim, Gary H. McClelland

Received February

and William D. Schulze*

1990. revised version received January

1991

Why do people pay taxes when they have an opportunity. even an incentive. IO evade? The experimental results in this paper suggest that tax compliance occurs because some individuals overweight the low probability of audit. although such overweighting is not universal. The results also indicate that compliance does not occur simply because individuals believe that evasion is wrong. since subject behavior is unchanged by the use of either neutral or loaded terms. Finally. there is evidence that individuals pay taxes because they value the public goods that their taxes linance. In short. individuals exhibit much diversity in their behavior.

I. Introduction In rcccnt years economists have dcvotcd incrcasinp attention to the study of individual tax evasion. Despite these efforts. our understanding of the reasons behind individual tax compliance behavior remains limited. In fitct, the puzzle of tax compliance is that most pcoplc continue to pay their taxes. This papa uses cxpcrimcntid methods factors play in the compliance dccision. One explanation punishment

is

to examine the role

that

various

for compliance strcsscs that the threat of dctcction and

responsible

for

complinnce.

This

theory

stems

from

the

economics-of-crime itpproach, based upon traditional expcctcd utility theory and first applied to titx evasion by Allingham and Sandmo (1972).’ Here a rational from

individual

is viewed as weighing the expected utility

successful tax evasion

with

the uncertain

of the benefits

prospect of detection and

punishment. and an individual pays taxes because he or she is afraid of getting caught. Although it is clear that detection and punishment affect compliance to ii dcgrec,* it is equally clear that these factors cannot explain all. or even most, tax compliance behavior. The percentage of individual Correspondmce ro: J.

Aim. University of Colorado. Boulder, CO 80309-0256. USA. ‘We wish Lo thank Charlie PIott, Mark Isaac. and Jorge Martinez for helpful comments on an earlier version of this paper. Mark Evrrs. Steve Elliot, and Julie Irwin provided excellent research assistance. ‘The basic model of Allingham and Sandmo (1972) has been extended in a variety of dimensions. See. for example. Yitzhaki (1974). Pencavel (19791. Sandmo (1981). Cowell (1985). and Alm (19X8). Cowell (1990) provides a comprehensive survey of the literalurr. ‘For empirical evidence on the deterrent &ccl of government audit and penalty policies. see Dubin and Wilde (19XX). 0057-2727.92,SOS.oO

3’) l992-Elsrvicr

Science Publishers B.V. All rights reserved

1.

22

A/m

er al.. Why do peoplepay mres.?

income tax returns that are subject to a thorough tax audit is quite small in the United States, less than I percent in recent years. In addition. the penalty on fraudulent

evasion in the United

States is only 75 percent of unpaid taxes,

and the penalties on non-fraudulent evasion are even less. A purely economic analysis of the evasion gamble implies that most individuals would evade if they are ‘rational’, because it is unlikely that cheaters will be caught and penalized.’ Yet compliance with the individual income tax remains relatively high; that is. individuals

pay far more in taxes than suggested by the

standard expected utility theory of compliance. It seems implausible that the low penalties and the low probability of detection that prevail in the United States. indeed in most countries, can by themselves act as an effective deterrent to evasion, unless individuals’ aversions to risk far exceed conventional assumptions. In fact, the Internal Revenue Service (1978) has found that there are numerous factors other than detection and punishment that affect the decision to pay taxes. It therefore appears that there is some discrepancy between the way in which people actually decide to pay their taxes and the models based on expcctcd utility theory that have been used by economists to explain this behavior. Such anomalous behavior has frcqucntly been found in other arcas of choice under uncertainty, particularly in those arcas that involve low probability-high

loss cvcnts, such as natural

or man-made

disasters, or in

those arcas whcrc the decisions of individuals arc intcrdcpcndcnt repcatcd. such as the voluntary provision of public goods. Scvcral explanations One argument

for this behavior

stems from thcorctical

and

have been suggcstcd in rcccnt years.

work of Machina

(1983) and Kahncman

%rartr and Wilde (19X5)and Skinner and Slemrod (19X5)make a simihlr nryumcnt. To illustrutc more prcciscly. consider the stand;ud cvas~on modrl of Allinyh;un and Sandmo (1972). Hcrc an individual receives a fixed cndowmant of income. I, and must choose how much of this income to declare IO the lax authorities and how much to under-report. The individual must pay taxes 31 thr rate I on every dolhlr D of income that is declared. while no 13xcs are paid on evaded income. tiowcvcr. the individual may be audited with probability p; if audited. then all unreported income is discovrrcd. and the individual must pay :I penalty a~ the rate 1’ on each dollar that he or she was supposed to pay in taxrs but did not pay, The individual’s incomr. I,. if caught under-reporting equ~ds I,=f -rD-l[r(l-01). while income. I,. if not caught is I, = I -rl). Expec~cd utility theory then assumes that the individual will choose D in order to maximize expected utility EU =pU(/,) +( I +p)U(/,). where U(,) is the utility function. Now suppose that this optimization is solved for specilic. realistic values of the various parameters and ti,r the spccitic utility runction. I,! -‘!‘I I -e). where the subscript i rcfcrs to the sta~c of the world (i =C.N) and c is 3 measure of the individual’s constant relative risk aversion. For ex;lmple, il r = 0.4. /’ = 2, p = 0.0 2. and e = I. then the individual will optimally declare no income. Very large valucx for rrlativrs risk aversion are rcquirrd IO generate compliance consistent with aclual U.S. experience. When e= 3. declared income is only I4 percent of true income: when e= 5. it is still only 44 percent; when c= IO. it is only 71 percent. Risk aversion must ctceed 30 for compliance to exceed 90 percent. However. existing ticld evidence suggests that c rangrs between one and two [Cohn et al. (1975). Friend and Blume (1975). Morin and Suarcz (19X3)]. Consequently. cxpeclcd utility theory predicts that the optimal strategy for most individuals is IO report littlr or no income. Tar Ices than is actu;dly observed.

J. Alm et al.. Why do

and Tversky either

(1979).

can

show

Using

great

different

sensitivity

pu.vta.re.~.7

peopie

approaches. to

or

can

they

23

argue

overweight

that low

individuals

probabilities.

Suppose. for example. that the true probability of an event is 0.02. In making their decisions, however, many individuals will systematically behave as if they

think

the likelihood

of the event

exceeds 0.02, when

viewed from an expected utility perspective. ties may therefore provide an additional taxpayers

give more

weight

to the probability

relative to an expected utility the level suggested by expected Another

factor

Overweighting explanation of an audit

model, then compliance utility theory.’

arises from

theoretical

and

their

behavior

is

of low probabilifor compliance. If than they ought will

experimental

be greater work

to

than

on public

good provision. Samuelson (19%) argued that the private provision of public goods will be inefficiently low because each individual will have an incentive to ‘free ride’

on the private

purchases

of others.

The

Samuelson

result

has

received some support from the experimental work of Kim and Walker (1984). Isaac, Walker and Thomas (1984). and Isaac, McCue and Plott (1985). However, other work argues that voluntary provision may not always play as a prisoners’ dilemma game; that is. an individual’s optimal decision may depend upon the actions that hc or she cxpccts others to follow, both now and in the future.’

Under

some circumstances.

full voluntary

tions (or cooperation) may be the dominant individual thcrcforc suggests that individuals pay taxes voluntarily

contribu-

strategy. This because they

work value

the goods

provided by govcrnmcnt and they rccognizc that their payment Howcvcr. the role of public may bc necessary to get others to contributc.h good provision in tax compliance has largely been ncglcctcd.’ The purpose of this paper is to use cxpcrimcntal methods to examine the ‘Studies of flood and carrhqudc insurance [Kunreuthcr cl aI (lY7X)j and of the vduc’ of avoiding cxp~urc IO hazardous suhst;mccs [f~urncss CI al. ( IYX.3). Smith and C~csvousgcs (1956)J alI suggestextraordinary lcvcls of risk aversion. Laboratory experiments by McClelland. Schulrr and Coursry ( IYX6) also confirm that individds oftsn overweight low probabilities when they have the opportunily IO purchase insurance IO protect against an uncertain loss of income. Marc generally. there is growing evidrnce from numerous areas tha[ indicarcs that individuals do not always behave in a manner consistent with cxpectrd utility theory. SW Machina (19X7) for a &tailed discussion of this li(erraturr. ‘For rxamplc, the theoretical work of Taylor (lY76). Axelrod (IYXJJ, Palfrey and Rocrnthnl (lW4). and Bagnoli and Lipman (1986) shows thar voluntary provision can lead to Ihe efiicirnl level of public good provision, despite the usual prrsumplion that individuals will attempt to frcr ride. The rxperimen[al litrralurr has mixed resulks. but there are numerous instances in which these theorrlicnl results hove hccn verified [Brubaker (19X2). Rapoporr (19X5).rrrd Uagnoli and McKee (IYYI)]. ‘There are. of course. other factors that may explain compliance. For example. psychologias and Other social scirntids argue that so&d norms and perceptions of fairness nlkcr compliancr; thar is, individuds pay taxes because they furl thal it is a social obligarion IO do so. although they comply less if they perceive th;ll they are tread less fairly than others. ‘Ser. however. Becker. Buchncr and Sleeking (19X7). who examine cxperimendly the role of transfer paymrnls on compliance. and Cowcll and Gordon (19xX). who analyze theoretically the dTcc[ of governmenl rxpcnditurcs on lax compliance and show Ihal a higher I;IX rale can Id IO less compliance.

J. Alm et

2‘4

roles that overweighting services

play

in

the

of..Why

do

people

of low probabilities individual’s

tax

pay taxes.? and recognition

compliance

of government

decision.

Experimental

methods have been applied to some issues in tax compliance by Friedland, Maital and Rutenberg (1978). Spicer and Becker (1980), Friedland (1982). Spicer and Hero (1985). and Becker. Buchner and Sleeking (1987). among others. In the experimental design used here, subjects are faced with a typical tax compliance decision: they receive income. they must decide how much income to report as taxable income, knowing that there is some probability that they will be caught and penalized if they do not report all of their income. and they receive a return

for

their

taxes (or a public good) that

depends upon the level of group tax payments. The parameters relevant to their decision - the tax rate, the probability of detection, and the like - are based upon values that individuals actually face. In particular, several levels for the probability of detection are used in separate treatments, with the values set at low levels, and several levels for the public good are also used in separate treatments. The experimental results provide strong evidence that some individuals overweight low probability events; that is, when the probability is non-zero but is low enough that evasion is the optimal strategy, the compliance far cxcccds the level predicted by expected utility

level of theory.

However, behavior is somewhat more complicated. For example, there is cvidcncc that individuals do not always exhibit ovcrwcighting or extreme risk aversion.

since

thcrc

is

still

some

compliuncc

when

the

probability

of

detection is zero and thcrc is still some evasion when individuals face a high enough probability to make full compliance the optimal strategy. The results also indicate that compliance behavior does not stem from a bclicf by subjects that evasion is wrong. Some cxpcrimcnts arc run twice. once with neutral terminology that makes no mention of taxes or evasion and instcnd treats the cxpcrimcnt simply as a risky decision, and once with instructions that clearly place the experiment in the context of tax evasion. Both treatments yield identical results. Finally, the results suggest that some individuals pay taxes bccausc they recognize that payment is necessary to receive government goods. An increase in the payoff that individuals rcccive from a given tax payment increases compliance, and compliance is positive and stable over time cvcn when the probability of detection is zero. Section 2 discusses the design of the expcrimcnts that examine the roles of overweighting and public goods in the compliance decision, and section 3 reports the results from the experiments. Summary and conclusions arc in section 4.

2. Experimental The

design

subjects used in the experiments

arc volunteers

drawn

from

undcr-

J. Alm et al.. Why do people pay taxes.7

graduate

classes at the University

to participate

of Colorado

only once in the experiment.’

3

at Boulder.

and are allowed

At the beginning

of a round.

each of the eight subjects is given one of eight incomes between SO.25 and 52.00 in SO.25 increments,

randomly

chosen by computer.

The subject must

decide how much income to report, and must pay taxes on all reported income at the rate of 40 percent. The subject pays no taxes on unreported income: however, the subject is told that there is some probability that his or her underreporting will be detected by an audit, at which point he or she must pay a penalty equal to 15 times all unpaid taxes.’ An audit is determined by the draw of a chip from a bag that contains a total of 100 red and white chips. If a red chip is drawn, an audit of all subjects occurs; if a white chip is drawn, no audit occurs. Three different levels of red and white chips are used in the experiments. After taxes arc paid and penalties if any are assessed, the total taxes paid by all subjects arc summed to give the ‘group tax fund’, increased by some multiple (or the ‘group surplus multiplier’) to reflect the consumers’ surplus that individuals

dcrivc from povcrnmcnt

provision of a public good. and then

divided equally among the subjects. Three different group surplus multipliers on the group tax fund arc used. The net balance for each subject is calculated (original income less taxes less pcnaltics plus share of the multiplied

group

tax fund).

A new round

then begins, with

the subject’s

balance carried over from the previous round. Subjects arc not allowed to communicate with one another during the cxpcrimcnt. At the completion of the cxpcrimcnt, the subject keeps all the money that hc or she has accumulated; each is guaranteed earnings arc typically botwccn conducted University

a minimum of $5.00 for participating, $ I5.00 and $25.00. The cxpcrimcnts

and arc

in the Laboratory for Economics and Psychology (LEAP) at the of Colorado. AII cntrics arc made and rccordcd on computer

terminals.

and

computer.

The cxpcrimcnt

all

calculations

arc

typically

pcrformcd

by

the

LEAP

MicroVAX

lasts less than one hour.

Thcrc arc six basic trcatmcnts, with ;I different set of subjects each time. Three sets of eight subjects face each of three different probabilities of audit during the experiment: 0 percent, 2 pcrccnt. and IO percent. The order in

“The instructions given IO subjects arc awil;~hlc upon rcquert. ‘A penalty multiphrr of IS times unpaid taxes may seem quite large. since actwl pcnaltics for incoms 1x1 fraud arc currently 75 percent of unpaid I~XL’S plus the unpaid taxes. However, it is important IO rccognirc that the di>covcry of fraud in one yrar Icclds IO Internal Rcvenuc Service (IRS) invcstigafion of potential fraud in previous years. The lncomc Tax Code (Section 6501 (C)) specilics that taxes 2nd penalties may he asscssrd al any time for fraud; that is, the IRS csn cxtcnd its investigation any numhcr of years in the ptls~ when it disrovcrs fraud. If. for example. the IRS cxtendcd its investigation for six years into the pss~.then the cfkctivr penalty multiplier is 10.5 (or 6x 1.75). When intcrcst penalties and. more significantly. legal costs arc also conridcrrd. a pentllty multiplwr of I5 does MI scum unreasonable. It also capture the type of catastrophtc loss that dctectwn of evasion okn brings.

‘6

3. Aim er al.. Why do Table Experimental

peoplepay taxrs? I design.’

Rounds Session

l-15

16-30

3135

lb

p=o

p = 0.02 p=O.lO

p=O.lO

m=O m=6 m=?

m=6 m=?

?b

p =

0.01

5

p=O.lO

‘4 5

m=2

6 -

m=O m=6

p=o

m=2 p=o p = 0.02 > p = 0.02

m=O >

‘In all sessions. the tax rate is 0.40. the penally rate is IS. and the individual’s share of the group fund is 1 R. %zssions 1. ? and 3 are run twice. once with and with loaded neutral once inslructions mstructions.

which the subjects fact those probabilities

is varied across sessions.

In the

first session the order is 0, 7, and IO pcrccnt; in the second session the order is 2. IO, and 0 pcrccnt; the order is IO, 0. and 2 pcrccnt in the third session. All subjects fact each probability for I5 rounds; they arc not told the number of rounds, although they arc told that the number of rounds is prcdctcrmined. The group surplus multiplier equals ?. in all of thcsc trcatmcnts. Three sets of tight

subjects also fact each of thrco diffcrcnt

lcvcls of the group

surplus multiplier. The lcvcls arc 0, 3, and 6. As with the probability, the order in which the subjects fact thcsc multipliers is varied across ssssions, and all subjects fact each multiplier for 15 rounds. The probability of dctcction equals 2 pcrccnt in itll of thcsc latter cxpcriments. The cxpcrimcntal design is summarized in table I. This cxpcrimcntal design is diffcrcnt in several rcspccts from previous cxpcrimcnts in tax compliance. “I Previous work has not always used values for the various policy parameters that approximate actual real-world values. In addition, some acccptcd proccduros of the cxpcrimcntal paradigm have not always been followed. Many of the results have not been verified by rcpcatcd rxpcrimcnts. Of perhaps more importance, previous work may have inadequately induced subject preferences because the instructions given to the subjects have placed the experiment squarely in the context of tax evasion; that is. the terminology used in all previous work may have provided an undcsirablc context to the experiments, and so the decision of the subjects may have reflected the values that they associate with such terms as ‘tax compliance’ or ‘tax evasion’, rather than the rewards or pcnaltics that ‘%e. for example. l.‘rlcdland (lYlc2). Spwx

Fricdland. Mailal and Rulenherg (lY7X). Spicer and Becker and ticro (lYN5). and Becker. Buchner and Sleeking (19X7).

(1980.

J. Alm er al.. l4’h.v do people pay tares?

they faced in the experiment in

the

compliance

per se. To explore

decision,

two

treatments

27

the role of such terminology are

examined,

one

that

uses

neutral Finally,

terminology and one that uses tax. or ‘loaded’. terminology.” most previous experimental work on tax evasion has not considered

the role

that

government

provision

of public

goods

plays

in tax compliance;

that is, individuals may voluntarily pay taxes to provide for public goods, even if there is no penalty on the failure to pay. because they recognize that they will recognize

receive something for their tax payments.” The experiments here that tax compliance may be affected by this exchange relationship

between the taxpayer and the government. Note that the optimal single-period strategy

for each subject

determined

maximize

implied

when by

the

expected

individual’s utility

goal

theory

in

is to the

special

can be easily

expected

case of

value,

as

a risk-neutral

individual who takes the actions of others as given (Cournot-Nash behavior). The expected value, Er! from the choice of how much income to report is

EV=f-tD+,ns(G+tD)-pJ‘[t(f-D)],

(1)

whcrc I is the individual’s tixcd income, D is dcclarcd income, G is taxes paid by all other group members. t is the tax rate on declared income, /’ is the tine rate on unpaid

taxes, p is the probability

of detection,

111is the group

surplus multiplier. and s is the individual’s share of the group tax fund. Maximization of cq. (I) by the choice of dcclarcd income f1 indicates that the individual will optimally report all income if

pj’ +

while When

the

IfIS

>

I,

individual

the group

(2

will surplus

report multiplier

zero

income equals

if the inequality

2 (and

the share

is reversed. of the public

good is 0.125), inequality (2) suggests that the dominant strategy for riskneutral individuals is to report zero income for the experiments in which the probability of detection is 0 and 2 percent, and to report all income when the probability is IO percent. More generally, the critical (or ‘cutoff’) level of the probability is 0.05 (=[ I-2 x O.lZS]/lS). However, if overweighting of low probabilities occurs, or if individuals bccomc extraordinarily risk averse at low probabilities, then there will be some compliance at 9 percent prob“The issue of loaded versus neu~rA instructions is discussed in more d&l b&w. “An exception is Rcckrr. Ruchner and !&eking (19X7). who examine the role of tmnsfer payments on compliancr.

Table 2 Average

groupcompliance

rate.

Probabihty

of audit (m = 2)

Treatment

p=o

p = 0.02

p=O.lO

XIesn, sessions I. 2. 3 Neutral instructions Loaded instructlons

0.200 0.189

0.503 0.522

0.675 0.672

Group

surplus

multiplier

Ip = 0.02) Mean. sessions 4. 5. 6

ability.

m=O

m=Z

m=6

0.435

0.537

0.592

even though it is less than the critical

probability.

Similarly.

probability of detection is 2 percent (and s = 0. IX), risk-neutral who behave according to the expected utility model should income for the treatments

when the individuals report zero

in which VI equals 0 and 3, and should

income when IPI equals 6.” relationship, then there will

report all

However, if subjects recognize the exchange bc some compliance at the lower multiplier

values.

3. Expcrirnental 3.1.

I’rohhility

The results

results

fj’mtfif for the variations

in the probability

of audit arc summarized

in

table 3. which gives the avcragc of the group compliance rates at each of the probnbilitics for the three groups. The average group compliance rate is calculated by dividing total reported income of all group members by total group income. Consider each of the three theory, the single-period

probabilities.

dominant

According

to expected utility

strategy for a risk-neutral

individual

is to

report zero income when the probability of detection is less than 5 percent. However, there is clearly substantial compliance at 2 percent probability. Compliance at p=O.O2 is on average 50.3 percent; the amount of compliance by group varies little, from 45.3 percent for group 3 to 48.1 percent for group I to 57.5 percent for group 2. Although expected utility theory is unable to explain this result, it is consistent with the overweighting of low probabilities that is suggested by Kahneman and Tversky (1979) or the extreme aversion to risk at low probabilities that is suggested by ivlachina (1983). As discussed below, compliance may also be motivated by the presence of the public good. “The

CUIOIT vaiuc for m is S.h( = [ I -0.02

x ISJO. 125).

J. Ah

er al.. Why do people

pay taxes?

In particular, coupling an enforcement mechanism may help overcome the free-rider problem. Even at p=O expected although Expected when the

there

is substantially

with

compliance

voluntary than

provision

is predicted

by

utility theory. The average group compliance is 20.0 percent. there is some variation across the three groups (5.3 to 35.8 percent). utility theory predicts that there will be zero reporting of income probability of detection is zero. This prediction is not observed,

due to the presence of the public be explained by overweighting detection

more

29

good. It is also clear that this result cannot or risk aversion, since the probability of

is zero.

Note, however, that compliance is actually less than that predicted by inequality (2) when p=O.l. When the probability is 0.1. the expected return to evasion

becomes

negative.

and

fully comply. However, the avcragc As with p=O. this behavior cannot

inequality

(2) predicts

that

subjects

will

group compliance is only 67.5 percent. be explained by overweighting or risk

aversion. Instead, subjects now appear to be risk-seeking, perhaps because of the guaranteed payment of $5.00. Also, some subjects may dismiss the likelihood of an audit bccausc of the relatively low level of the probability, even though it exceeds the critical level, and some subjects ride due to the prcscncc of the public good. The

rate

of compliance

rises in a non-linear

way

as the

may

try

to free

probability

of

detection increases; that efforts, but this payoff

is. tax rcvenucs increase with grcatcr enforcement dcclincs as the probability incrcascs. At p=O, compliance is 20.0 pcrccnt; the compliance rate incrcascs significantly to 50.2 Thcsc pcrccnt at p = 0.02, and then rises but only to 67.5 percent at p=O.l. differcnccs arc highly statistically significant.14

‘*Statistical ;mdysis of the diffcrencc in mc;ms rcquircs that the observations be normal and independent. Scvcral alkrnativc approxhcs arc followed to gener:lle average complisncc rates that satisfy thcsc requircmcnts. In the lirst approxh. Ihc round is trc:lted as the unit of observation. The average compliance raft for a given round is cdcula~cd by averaging for each round the compliance rats across all right subjects in all three replications of a given probability; this procedure generates 45 IOI~I obscrvdtons. or one for each of the fifteen rounds fur each ol the three probabilities. The sample I~SI st;ltistic for the difTercnce between the average compliance rates JI p=O and p=O.O2 is 16.56. and is 8.60 for rhc di!Tcrcncc bctwecn the average compliance rdcs ;II p =0.02 and p = 0. I; the critical value of the r-statistic is 2.47 for a one-&led ICSI 31 the 0.01 significance level with 28 degrees of freedom. In the second and more conservative approach, the group is treated as the unit of analysis. Here the average compliance rate IS calcula~cd by averaging across all right subjects und all liken rounds in a given group for each probabdity level; this approach generates 9 total observations, or one fur each of the three groups at each of the three problrbiliries. Bccausc there may be non-independence induced by having the same subjects a~ each of the three probabilities. difkrencc scores arc then calcula~cd, so that there is only one dirercncr for each group. For example, the sample test slarisuc for the dillcrcncc between the average compliance rates 31 p =O and p =0.02 is computed by first calculaling for each group the difTercncc between rhc compliance rates DI p=O and p =O.OZ. and then using these three differences IO form the sample test statistic; the resulting I~SI statistic is 5.69. The ICSI statistic for p=O.O2 versus p=O.l equals 4.1 I. Both difkrenccs arc highly significant.

J. Ah

30

Fig.

er al.. Why do

peoplepay tars”

I gives a more dctailcd picture of the avcragc amount of compliance

by round for the three probnbilitics.

When

the probability

of dctcction is 0,

thcrc is substantial compliance and the amount of compliance dots not decay as the cxpcrimcnt proceeds. I5 This . trcntment corresponds to the voluntary

provision

of public good cxpcrimcnts - there is no penalty on non-

payment of taxcs - so that the results hcrc may bc compared with those from the public good literature. In particular, the results contrast with those of Isaac, McCuc and Plott

(19X5). in which they find funding

lcvcls for the

public good that arc near zero and that decay with rcpcatcd rounds. Here there is substantial compliance that dots not on avcragc fall in later rounds. Fig.

I also shows compliance by round when the probability

of dctcction

is 0.02. Although the dominant stratcpy from cxpcctcd utility theory is to evade. the average group compliance rate is 50.3 percent, and this does not vary much by round. On the other hand, compliance is lower than that predicted by cxpcctcd utility theory when p=O.l. Fig. L clearly shows that the level of compliance increases with the probability of dctcction. It also demonstrates that the predictions of a riskneutral version of cxpectcd utility theory arc not vorificd: thcrc is grcatcr compliance at low probabilities (p=O and p=O.O2) and less compliance at Hidden within fig. 2 is some individual variation in compliance across “Thcrc is. howcvcr. romc variation xross groups. In groups widely. Appurcntly some suhjccts cqxrimcnkd with tar payments follow: when others dd not follow. maws Ml IO zero.

I

and 3. compliance tluc~ua~cs in the hop Ihal others would

1.

Aim

et al.. Why

do people pay taxes?

31

60

50

40

30

20

10

0 0

0.1

0.2

0.3

Fraction

0.4

0.5

of

0.6

Income

0.7

0.6

0.9

1

Declared

Fig. 2

high probabilities (p=O.I) way in which individuals

than is predicted by cxpcctcd utility theory. The actually weight the probability of an uncertain

event is apparently not the way that is assumed under expected utility t hcory. It is also of some intcrcst to cxamine the individual data. Fig. 3 presents the frcqucncy distribution of the individual compliance rates for the three probability trcatmcnts.“’ Thcrc is much cvidcncc of all-or-none behavior, as would result from any linear (or risk-neutral) individual. Overall, 67 percent of the individual Howcvcr, this varies with the probability

payoff function for the decisions arc all-or-none.

of detection. When p=O. 7X pcrccnt

arc all-or-none; for p=O.O2 this drops to 64 pcrccnt. and it drops still further to 61 pcrccnt for p=O.l. Recall, however, that (risk-neutral)

cxpcctcd utility

theory predicts that the

cut-off lcvcl for the probability of detection is 0.05: when ~~0.05, compliance should be 0, while compliance should be complete when p>O.O5. These predictions are complctcly rejcctcd by the results. It therefore appears that individuals are largely risk neutral and rationally select and follow a cutoff rule. However, many do not use expcctcd utility theory in the selection of that cutoff value. rounds. A subject apparently may try different strategies in the compliance game in nn attempt. for example, to induce others in the group to comply. Recall that the subjects know the size of the group fund at the end of each lbFor each Irwtment lhcrr arc 360 observations. or three replications timcs right subjects times IS rounds. The individual compliance rate for any round equals declared income divided by true income.

J. Ah et al., Why do people

32

pay tares.”

“OI

0.9 J

06-

(4

0.1 -

mr6

1

0.0 1 0

2

4

6

6

10

12

14

5

Round Fig. 3

round, so they can dctcrmins decision

to report

more

whcthcr other group mcmbcrs respond to their

income (and they ciln

infer

whcthcr

others

arc

complying or cheating). Thcrc is in fact a positive and significant correlation bctwccn each individual’s compliance rate in ;I given round and the amount of the public good rcccivcd in the previous round.” Eventually. howcvcr, nearly all subjects scttlc into ;I stable strategy. and their compliance dots not fluctuate. Subjects also gcncrally bchavc consistently

across the three diffcr-

cnt levels of probability. Thcrc arc virtually no instances in which ;I subject complies at p = 0 or p = 0.03 and cvadcs at p = 0. I, or vice versa.

The results for the group surplus multiplier arc summarized in table 2 and in figs. 3 and 4. Recall that under expected utility theory the sin&period dominant strategy for ;L risk-neutral individual is to cvadc fully when the multiplier equals 0 and 2 and to comply fully when IPI = 6. These predictions “This rcsuh c‘onfr;rsfs somewhat with that of Spicer and Hero (I9XSj. who found in their experiments Ihat an individual’s compliance did not depend upon his or her pcrcep(ion of the comphancc behavior of others. However. in their experiments subjects dtd not know how other mcmhcrs of rhcir group actually hchaved. since (heir perceptions were had upon drcuptivr informntion provided by the experimenters ahoul average group compliance rates In cxpcrimcnrs that were not m &I run. Also. suhjccls in their cxpcrimcnts were not ahlc IO AXI the behavior of other group members by their own compliance decisions, since there was no group tax fund and (hew was no interaction among the group mcmhers.

J. Aim et (11..Why do people

0

0.2

0.I

0.3

Fraction

0.4

of

0.5

pay taxes?

0.6

Income

0.7

33

0.6

0.9

1

Declared

Fig. 4

arc not supported

by the results.

Compliance

fitlls is 0 and 2, ,md .

the multiplier

below

signiticantly

full

cxcceds zero

compliance

when

when

the multiplier

is 6. The

trcatmont

cxpcrimcnts, substantial rate

in

since

compliance

cqual

to 43.5

dctcction

;md

dctcction

(p=O.O2).

cxpcctcd

utility

higher is

avcragc

grcatcr.

riding. various

further.

possibly

The

of 53.7

under

;Lrc identical. but

only

of

provision

carlicr

tax

is motivated

ovcrwcight which pcrccnt),

enforccmcnt, mechanism

percent

the earlier

low

to 59.2

percent.

dismissal

m=2

level

Thcrc by fear

probability

by

an

cvcn

to taxes

overweighting

of

low

to overcome

treatment

of of

predicted

gcncratcs

helps

is

compliance

since the payoff

is not statistically

probability

increase

group solely

the

cxcccd the zero in

compliance

payments.

hcrc

An

due to risk-seeking.

most

the avcragc

rate (53.7

combination

their

with

will

trcatmcnt

to

for

individuals

compliance

compliance percent’

nothing

Compliance If

compliance

the

that (50.3

corresponds

trc:ttmcnt,

3 voluntary

paramctcrs

compliance rr1=6,

then

theory.

and

Note

in this

psrccnt.

group

m=O rcccivc

punishment.

Again.

probabilities, complinncc

which

subjects

different

frccfrom

in which

the

in the multiplier

to 6 incrcascs

There

compliance

is not

of the (low)

full

probability

;Lt

of audit,

or free-riding.“’ ‘“As with the probaility sessions. IWO alternative approaches are used to analyze the average compliance ralrs (see footnote 14). When the round is the unit of andysis. so that there are 45 IOI:I~ observations. rhere arc signilicanl dillcrencrs between the average compliance rates ~1 m =O and m = 2 (I-slalistic = 5.74). and al m = 2 dnd m = 6 (f-ctaGstic = 2.79). When the group is kated

These

results

demonstrate

that

compliance

increases

with

the

group

surplus multiplier. and suggest that government can increase compliance by providing goods that their citizens prefer more. by providing these goods in a more efficient

manner,

or by more effectively

emphasizing

that

taxes are

necessary for receipt of government services. However, although compliance increases with m, the increase is non-linear. As with the probability of detection, there appear to be limits

on how much governments

can affect

compliance by increasing the individual payoff to tax payments. Compliance by round for the three levels of the multiplier is shown in fig. 2. There is substantial variation in the average group compliance rate, especially for m = 0 and VI = 6. However. this variability does not exhibit any trend: that is, there is no systematic tendency for compliance to rise or to fall as the experiment

proceeds. More importantly.

fig. 3 demonstrates

again that

with few exceptions compliance is greater when the group surplus multiplier is greater. Individuals pay more in taxes when they receive more for their tax payments. The frcquoncy distribution of individual compliance rates is shown in fig. 4. As with fig. 2. the compliance behavior tends to be all-or-none. with 60 pcrccnt

of

all

decisions

in

these

categories.

somcwhat wcakcr than in the probability

although

trcatmcnts.

this

tendency

is

Fig. 4 also shows that a

risk-neutral version of expected utility theory is not supported by the results. Again, most individuals follow a cutofT rule in their compliance behavior, but their behavior suggests that they do not use cxpcctcd utility theory in the dctcrmination of the cutoff value. Individual subjects also bchavc consistently across the throc group surplus multipliers, cvmpliancc when the multiplier incroascs.

increasing (or not dccrcasing) their

As discussed

carlicr. all previous cxpcrimcntal work on tax evasion has instructions that make it clear to subjects that they are participating in a tax compliance game. Unfortunately, use of such loaded instructions may used

lead to unpredictable results. since subjects may respond to the values they associate with the loaded terms rather than to the incentives in the experiment itsclc that is, loaded instructions may lead to context effects that can inllucncc the results in unpredictable ways [Kahneman and Tvcrsky (1979). Machina (1987)]. Concern with framing cfTects has led most expcrimcntalists to USC it neutral terminology, one that masks the context of the experiment and that gives the experimenter more control over the laboratory setting. However. thcrc are few studies in experimental economics that have

J.

Aim

et ul.. W’hy do people

directly examined whether results instructions: This

pup faxes.?

35

are affected by the use of loaded or neutral

there are no evasion experiments

that have examined this issue.

section looks at this issue by comparing two treatments (see table I). In

the additional treatment described here. the instructions

include loaded terms

like taxes. audit, reported income. and penalty; in the base treatment. a neutral terminology was used (payment. check, disclosed money. shortfall). In experimental instructions, context effects might occur because the use of

loaded

words and the inclusion

invoke different ‘mental scripts’.

of irrelevant material may lead subjects to which enable the subject to till in missing

information in the instructions but which also may unpredictably influence subject choices. Of course. the more explicit and complete the instructions. even in the presence of loaded terms, the less will subjects have to rely on scripts to fill in missing information. In this case it seems likely that there should be little difference between loaded and neutral instructions. This

reasoning

information

suggests

on the situation

that if subjects

are given complete and precise

they face in the laboratory

- as they are in the

experiments here - then scripts should not bc needed to help subjects till in missing context. Since the context is already complete, the USC of potentially loaded words such as tax. audit, or penalty should

have no impact on the

behavior of subjects relative to a treatment that does not WC such words. Note, howcvcr. that if true uncertainty is present in an experiment (say, prohahilities arc unknown), loaded words may call up scripts that suggcsl the probability Icvcl and so affect choices. The results arc summarized in table 2, which gives the average group compliance

rate across

trcatmcnts.

for

each of the three

probabilities.“’

Trcatmcnts using loaded and neutral instructions give results virtually identical. Dcbricfing of subjccls in the neutral terminology

that arc treatment

also suggcstcd. somewhat surprisingly, that Ihey did not realize that they had participated in a ‘tax’ cxpcrimcnt. Thus, although the conlcxt apparently dill&s

for subjects in the two trcatmcnts, subjects arc not forced to rely upon

their own scripts (i.e. real-world knowlcdgc of the tax system) to complete the context because in both trcalmcnts they are given identical and full information on the parameters relevant to their choices, including probabilitics of audit. Consequently, their behavior is unaffcctod by the nature of the instructions. This result implies that previous compliance experiments may not have been substantially affected by their use of loaded terms. at Ieast if they provided complctc information on the situation facing subjects.

4. Conclusions Why

do people pay taxes

when they

have an opportunity,

even an

incentive.

to evade?

compliance weight with their taxes

occurs

the low

The experimental because

probability

some

results

of audit

that

than

a simple there

overweighting

application

they

or

to extreme

risk

does not behavior Finally,

occur

from

a belief

suggest

oversensitive

that

to

in fact face. When

or

combined

that

utility

theory

compliance

aversion,

since

is not

there

would

suggest.

always

is some

due to

compliance

and there is some evasion when the is negative. Furthermore, compliance

by subjects

that

evasion

is wrong,

since their

is unchanged by the use of either loaded or neutral instructions. the results suggest that compliance occurs because some individuals

the public

goods

that

their

amount that individuals receive compliance rate, and individuals

tax

payments

from a given pay something

finance.

An increase

in the

tax payment increases their in taxes to receive govern-

mcnt services even when there is no chance of detection and punishment. In short. individuals exhibit a remarkable diversity in behavior. somctimcs appear to ovcrwcight low probabilities. bc risk-seeking, they arc on occasion coopcrativc, free-riders. Whcthcr any theory of compliance such behavior is unknown at present. However, theory

tax over-

individuals do not behave as if Rather, they often pay more in

of expected

is also some evidence

when there is no chance of detection expected value of the evasion gamble

value

are

the high penalty on detected evasion, preferences are linear in probabilities.

However.

in this paper

individuals

is nccdod. one can then dual with

or arc dealt

with

unsatisfactorily

can bc dcvclopcd to explain it is apparent that some new

those factors

by cxpcctcd

They

they sometimes appear to and at other times they are

utility

that arc either

ignored

lhcory.

Hefwenccs AIlingham. \llch;wl G. ;~nd Agnar Sandmo. lY72. Income lax ewsion: A thcorelicd analysis. Journal of Public liconomlcs I. 323-338. Aim. James. IYM. Compliance CO\I~ nnd rhr IU ;Ivod;mcc I;IK cvasiun decision. Public I.‘inance Quarlcrly 16. no. I, 33 6’). Awlrod. R.. IYXJ, The e\olulion of cooperation (Basic Books. New York). B;lynoli. .LlJrk ;mJ B.L. Lipman. IYXh. Can private provision of public goods bc rllicicnt?. llniverslty of ,Mlchlgan Working paper. i%;lgnoli, %f;Irk and Xlichacl McKee. lY91. Vdunrury contrihulion games: ElTicicnr private proviwn of puhl~c goods. IGxmomic Inquiry 29. no. 2. 351 -366. Rcckcr. Winlfrd. tIcIn/-Jurgcn Buchncr and Simon Sleeking. 1997, The impact of public transfer sxpcndilurc\ on tax cvaswn: An rxperimenral approach, Journal of Public &onomits 34. 243-251. Bruhakcr. Ed. IYXZ. Sixty-cighr percent free rrvelntion and thirty-two percent free ride’! Demxd disclosurw under varying conditions on exclusion. in: Vernon L. Smith, cd., Research in Experimcnlal ilconomics. vol. Z (JAI Press. Greenwich. CT). 19X3. Valuing policies which Rurncss. CI S.. R.C. Cummings. A.F. \lchr and b1.S. Walhcrl. reduce cn~lronmcnfal risk, Natural Rrsourccs Journal 23. 676-682.

J. Afm et al.. Why do

people

pay taxes?

37

Cohn. Richard A.. Wilbur G. Lewellen, Ronald C. Lease and Gary G. Schlarbaum. 1975. Individual investor risk aversion and investment portfolio composition, Journal of Finance 30. 60.~620. Cowell. Frank A., 1985. Tax evasion with labour income. Journal of Public Economics 26. 19-34. Cowell. Frank A.. 1990. Cheating the government: The economics of evasion (MIT Press. Cambridge. MA). Cowell. Frank A. and James P.F. Gordon. 1988, Unwillingness to pay: Tax evasion and public good provision. Journal of Public Economics 36. 30%3?1. Dubin. Jeffrey A. and Louis L. Wilde. 1988. An empirical analysis of federal income tan auditing and compliance. National Tan Journal 41. no. I. 61-74. Friedland. Nehemiah. 1982. A note on tar evasion as a function of the quality of information abtiut the credibdity of threatened fmes: Some preliminary research. Journal of Applied Social Psychology 12. 54-59. Fnedland. Nehemiah. Shlomo Xlaital and Aryeh Rutenberg. 197X. A simulation study of income tax evasion. Journal of Public Econom& IO. 107-l 16: Friend. lrwm and %larshall E. Blume. 1975. The demand for risky assets. American Economic Review 65. 90&92. Graetz. Michael J. and Louis L. Wilde. 198.5. The economics of tax compliance: Fact and fantasy. National Tax Journal 3X. no. 3. 355-363. Internal Revenue Service. United States Department of the Treasury, 197X. A dictionary of compliance factors (Government Printing Oflice. Washington. D.C.). Isaac. R. Mark. Kenneth F. McCue and Charles R. Plott. 19X5. Public goods provision in an experimental environment. Journal of Public Economics 26. 51-74. Isaac. R. Mark. J.&l. Walker and S. Thomas. 19X4. Divergent evidence on free-riding: An experimental examination of possible explanations. public Choice 43. I IZ-149. Kahncman, Daniel and Amos Tversky. lY79. Prospect theory: An analysis of decision under risk, Econometrica 47. 263-291. Kim, 0. and M. Walker. IYHJ. The free rider problem: Experimental evidcncc. Public Choice 43. 3-24. Kunrcuther. H.. R. Ginxiherg. L. IMiller. P. Sapi. P. Slavic, B. Borkan and N. Katz. 107X. Disaster insurances protc&on: public pohcy lessons (John Wiley and Sons. Inc.. New York. NY). Machina. Mark J.. 19X.3. Gcneralixd expected utihty analysis and the nature of oh*erved violations of the mdcpcndcnce axiom. in: Bcrnt Stigum and I‘rcd Wcnstop. cds.. I:ound:~trons of utility and risk theory with applications (I). Rcidel. Dordrccht. Holland). Machina. Mark 1.. IYX7. Choice under uncertainty: Problems solved and unsolved, Journal of Economic f’crspcclives I, no. I. I21 -1%. McClelland. Gary II.. William D. Schulle and Don L. Coursey. 19X6. Valuing risk: A ctrmparison of expected utility with models from cognitive psychology. unpublished manuscript. University 0r Colorxlo. Boulder. CO. Morin. Kogrr A. and A. I:ernandcr SuareL 1983. Risk aversion revisited, Journal of Finance 3X. 1201-1316. Palfrey. T. and t1. Rosenthal. 19X-t. Participation and the provision of discrele public goods. Journal of Public Economics 24, I71 -193. Pencavel. John H.. IY79. A note on income tax evasion. labor supply, and nonlinear tax schedules. Journal of Public Economic 12. 115-124. Rapoport. Amnon. 1985. Provision of public goods and the MCS experimental paradigm. American Political Science Review 7Y, I-IX-ISS. Samuelson. Paul, 1954. The pure theory of public expenditure. Review of Economics and Statistics 36, 3X7-390. Sandmo. Agnar. 19X1. Income tax evasion. labor supply. and the equity-efficiency tradeoff, Journal of Public Economics 16. 265-2xX. Skinner, Jonathan and Joel Slemrod. IYYS. An economic perspective on tax evasion, National Tax Journal 3X. no. 3. 345-353. Smith, V. Kerry and William H. Desvouspes. IYX6. Asymmetries in the valuation of risk and the siting of hazardous waste faciltties, American Economic Review Papers and Proceedings 76, 29 I -2Y.t.

38

J.

Aim

et

al..

U’hy

do

people

puy

roes?

Spicer. Michael W. and Lee Becker. 19X0. Fiscal inequity and tax evasion: approach. Nntlonul Trir Journal 33. no. 2. 171-175. Spicer, Mwhuel W. and Rodney E. Hero. IYL(S. Tax evwon and heuristics. Economics 26. 263-267. Taylor. 51.. 1976. Anarchy and Cooperation (John Wdey and Sons. Fl;ew York. Yitzhahi. Sholomo. 1974. A note on income tax evasion: A theoretical analysis. Econamlcs 3._‘01 -‘O’. __

An experimental Journal NY). Journal

of Public

of Public